List of set identities and relations

This article lists mathematical properties and laws of sets, involving the set-theoretic operations of union, intersection, and complementation and the relations of set equality and set inclusion. It also provides systematic procedures for evaluating expressions, and performing calculations, involving these operations and relations.

The binary operations of set union () and intersection () satisfy many identities. Several of these identities or "laws" have well established names.

Notation

Throughout this article, capital letters such as and will denote sets and will denote the power set of If it is needed then unless indicated otherwise, it should be assumed that denotes the universe set, which means that all sets that are used in the formula are subsets of In particular, the complement of a set will be denoted by where unless indicated otherwise, it should be assumed that denotes the complement of in (the universe)

Typically, the set will denote the Left most set, the Middle set, and the Right most set.

For sets and define:

and

The symmetric difference of and is:[1][2]

If is a set that is understood (say from context, or because it is clearly stated) to be a subset of some other set then the complement of a set may be denoted by:

The definition of may depend on context. For instance, had been declared as a subset of with the sets and not necessarily related to each other in any way, then would likely mean instead of

Finitely many sets and the algebra of sets

A family of subsets of a set is said to be an algebra of sets if and for all all three of the sets and are elements of [3] The article on this topic lists set identities and other relationships these three operations.

Every algebra of sets is also a ring of sets[3] and a π-system.

Algebra generated by a family of sets

Given any family of subsets of there is a unique smallest[note 1] algebra of sets in containing [3] It is called the algebra generated by and it will be denote it by This algebra can be constructed as follows:[3]

  1. If then and we are done. Alternatively, if is empty then may be replaced with and continue with the construction.
  2. Let be the family of all sets in together with their complements (taken in ).
  3. Let be the family of all possible finite intersections of sets in [note 2]
  4. Then the algebra generated by is the set consisting of all possible finite unions of sets in

One subset involved

Assume

Identity:[4]

but

so

Idempotence[4] and Nilpotence:

Domination:[4]

but

so

Double complement or involution law:

[4]

[4]

Other properties:

If is any set then the following are equivalent:

  1. is not empty (), meaning:
  2. (In classical mathematics) is inhabited, meaning:
    • In constructive mathematics, "not empty" and "inhabited" are not equivalent: every inhabited set is not empty but the converse is not always guaranteed; that is, in constructive mathematics, a set that is not empty (where by definition, " is empty" means that the statement is true) might not have an inhabitant (which is an such that ).
  3. for some set

If is any set then the following are equivalent:

  1. is empty (), meaning:
  2. for every set
  3. for every set
  4. for some/every set

Two sets involved

In the left hand sides of the following identities, is the Left most set and is the Right most set. Assume both are subsets of some universe set

Elementary operations characterized

In the left hand sides of the following identities, is the Left most set and is the Right most set. Whenever necessary, both should be assumed to be subsets of some universe set so that

Properties involving two sets

De Morgan's laws:

For

Absorption laws:

Commutativity:[4]

Set subtraction is not commutative. However, the commutativity of set subtraction can be characterized: from it follows that:

Said differently, if distinct symbols always represented distinct sets, then the only true formulas of the form that could be written would be those involving a single symbol; that is, those of the form: But such formulas are necessarily true for every binary operation (because must hold by definition of equality), and so in this sense, set subtraction is as diametrically opposite to being commutative as is possible for a binary operation. Set subtraction is also neither left alternative nor right alternative; instead, if and only if if and only if Set subtraction is quasi-commutative and satisfies the Jordan identity.

Other properties

  • Given any
  • If then
  • If then:

The following statements are equivalent:

Subset inclusion

The following statements are equivalent for any [4]

  1. (that is, )

The following statements are equivalent for any

  1. There exists some
Meets, Joint, and lattice properties

Inclusion is a partial order: Explicitly, this means that inclusion which is a binary operation, has the following three properties:[4]

  • Reflexivity:
  • Antisymmetry:
  • Transitivity:

The following proposition says that for any set the power set of ordered by inclusion, is a bounded lattice, and hence together with the distributive and complement laws above, show that it is a Boolean algebra.

Existence of a least element and a greatest element:

Joins/supremums exist:[4]

The union is the join/supremum of and with respect to because:

  1. and and
  2. if is a set such that and then

The intersection is the join/supremum of and with respect to

Meets/infimums exist:[4]

The intersection is the meet/infimum of and with respect to because:

  1. if and and
  2. if is a set such that and then

The union is the meet/infimum of and with respect to

Other inclusion properties:

  • If and then [4]
  • if and only if or

Three sets involved

In the left hand sides of the following identities, is the Left most set, is the Middle set, and is the Right most set.

Precedence rules

There is no universal agreement on the order of precedence of the basic set operators. Nevertheless, many authors use precedence rules for set operators, although these rules vary with the author.

One common convention is to associate intersection with logical conjunction (and) and associate union with logical disjunction (or) and then transfer the precedence of these logical operators (where has precedence over ) to these set operators, thereby giving precedence over So for example, would mean since it would be associated with the logical statement and similarly, would mean since it would be associated with

Sometimes, set complement (subtraction) is also associated with logical complement (not) in which case it will have the highest precedence. More specifically, is rewritten so that for example, would mean since it would be rewritten as the logical statement which is equal to For another example, because means which is equal to both and (where was rewritten as ), the formula would refer to the set moreover, since this set is also equal to (other set identities can similarly be deduced from propositional calculus identities in this way). However, because set subtraction is not associative a formula such as would be ambiguous; for this reason, among others, set subtraction is often not assigned any precedence at all.

Symmetric difference is sometimes associated with exclusive or (xor) (also sometimes denoted by ), in which case if the order of precedence from highest to lowest is then the order of precedence (from highest to lowest) for the set operators would be There is no universal agreement on the precedence of exclusive disjunction with respect to the other logical connectives, which is why symmetric difference is not often assigned a precedence.

Associativity

Definition: A binary operator is called associative if always holds.

The following set operators are associative:[4]

For set subtraction, instead of associativity, only the following is always guaranteed:

where equality holds if and only if (this condition does not depend on ). Thus if and only if where the only difference between the left and right hand side set equalities is that the locations of have been swapped.

Distributivity

Definition: If are binary operators then left distributes over if

while right distributes over if

The operator distributes over if it both left distributes and right distributes over In the definitions above, to transform one side to the other, the innermost operator (the operator inside the parentheses) becomes the outermost operator and the outermost operator becomes the innermost operator.

Right distributivity:[4]

Left distributivity:[4]

Failure of set subtraction to left distribute:

Set subtraction is right distributive over itself. However, set subtraction is not left distributive over itself because only the following is guaranteed in general:

where equality holds if and only if which happens if and only if

For symmetric difference, the sets and are always disjoint. So these two sets are equal if and only if they are both equal to Moreover, if and only if

To investigate the left distributivity of set subtraction over unions or intersections, consider how the sets involved in (both of) De Morgan's laws are all related:

always holds in general but equality is not guaranteed. Equality holds if and only if which happens if and only if

This observation about De Morgan's laws shows that is not left distributive over or because only the following are guaranteed in general:

where equality holds for one (or equivalently, for both) of the above two inclusion formulas if and only if

The following statements are equivalent:

  1. that is, left distributes over for these three particular sets
  2. that is, left distributes over for these three particular sets
  3. and

Quasi-commutativity:

always holds but in general,

However, if and only if if and only if

Distributivity and symmetric difference:

Intersection distributes over symmetric difference:

Union does not distribute over symmetric difference because only the following is guaranteed in general:

Symmetric difference does not distribute over itself:

and in general, for any sets (where represents ), might not be a subset, nor a superset, of (and the same is true for ).

Set subtraction complexity: To manage the many identities involving set subtraction, this section is divided based on where the set subtraction operation and parentheses are located on the left hand side of the identity. The great variety and (relative) complexity of formulas involving set subtraction (compared to those without it) is in part due to the fact that unlike and set subtraction is neither associative nor commutative and it also is not left distributive over or even over itself.

Both operators are set subtraction

  • If
  • with equality if and only if

Set subtraction on the left

Parentheses on the left

[5]

Parentheses on the right

Set subtraction on the right

Parentheses on the left

Parentheses on the right

[5]

Three operators

Operations of the form :

Operations of the form :

Operations of the form :

Other properties:

  • If then [5]
  • If then
  • if and only if for any belongs to at most two of the sets

Arbitrary families of sets

Let and be families of sets. Whenever the assumption is needed, then all indexing sets, such as and are assumed to be non-empty.

Definitions

Arbitrary unions defined

[4]

 

 

 

 

(Def. 1)

If then which is somethings called the nullary union convention (despite being called a convention, this equality follows from the definition).

Arbitrary intersections defined

If then[4]

 

 

 

 

(Def. 2)

Nullary intersections

If then

where every possible thing in the universe vacuously satisfied the condition: "if then ". Consequently, consists of everything in the universe.

So if and:

  1. if you are working in a model in which there exists some universe set then
  2. otherwise, if you are working in a model in which "the class of all things " is not a set (by far the most common situation) then is undefined because consists of everything, which makes a proper class and not a set.
Assumption: Henceforth, whenever a formula requires some indexing set to be non-empty in order for an arbitrary intersection to be well-defined, then this will automatically be assumed without mention.

A consequence of this is the following assumption/definition:

A finite intersection of sets or an intersection of finitely many sets refers to the intersection of a finite collection of one or more sets.

Some authors adopt the so called nullary intersection convention, which is the convention that an empty intersection of sets is equal to some canonical set. In particular, if all sets are subsets of some set then some author may declare that the empty intersection of these sets be equal to However, the nullary intersection convention is not as commonly accepted as the nullary union convention and this article will not adopt it (this is due to the fact that unlike the empty union, the value of the empty intersection depends on so if there are multiple sets under consideration, which is commonly the case, then the value of the empty intersection risks becoming ambiguous).

Multiple index sets

Commutativity and associativity

Commutativity:[4]

Unions of unions and intersections of intersections:[4]

[4]

 

 

 

 

(Eq. 2a)

[4]

 

 

 

 

(Eq. 2b)

and if then also:[note 3]

[4]

 

 

 

 

(Eq. 2c)

[4]

 

 

 

 

(Eq. 2d)

Binary intersection of arbitrary unions

 

 

 

 

(Eq. 3a)

[5]

 

 

 

 

(Eq. 3b)

  • If all are pairwise disjoint and all are also pairwise disjoint, then so are all (that is, if then ).

  • Importantly, if then in general,
    (see this[note 4] footnote for an example). The single union on the right hand side must be over all pairs
    The same is usually true for other similar non-trivial set equalities and relations that depend on two (potentially unrelated) indexing sets and (such as Eq. 4b or Eq. 7g[5]). Two exceptions are Eq. 2c (unions of unions) and Eq. 2d (intersections of intersections), but both of these are among the most trivial of set equalities and moreover, even for these equalities there is still something that must be proven.[note 3]

Binary union of arbitrary intersections

 

 

 

 

(Eq. 4a)

[5]

 

 

 

 

(Eq. 4b)

Arbitrary intersections and arbitrary unions

Naively swapping and may produce a different set

The following inclusion always holds:

 

 

 

 

(Inclusion 1 ∪∩ is a subset of ∩∪)

In general, equality need not hold and moreover, the right hand side depends on how, for each fixed the sets are labelled (see this footnote[note 5] for an example) and the analogous statement is also true of the left hand side as well. Equality can hold under certain circumstances, such as in 7e and 7f, which are respectively the special cases where and (for 7f, and are swapped). For a correct formula that extends the distributive laws, an approach other than just switching and is needed.

Distributive laws

Suppose that for each is a non-empty index set and for each let be any set (for example, to apply this law to use for all and use for all and all ). Let

denote the Cartesian product, which can be interpreted as the set of all functions such that for every Then

 

 

 

 

(Eq. 5 ∩∪ to ∪∩)

 

 

 

 

(Eq. 6 ∪∩ to ∩∪)

where


Example application: In the particular case where all are equal (that is, for all which is the case with the family for example), then letting denote this common set, the Cartesian product will be which is the set of all functions of the form The above set equalities Eq. 5 ∩∪ to ∪∩ and Eq. 6 ∪∩ to ∩∪, respectively become:

  • [4]
  • [4]

which when combined with Inclusion 1 ∪∩ is a subset of ∩∪ implies:

where

  • on the left hand side, the indices range over (so the subscripts of range over )
  • on the right hand side, the indices range over (so the subscripts of range over ).


Example application: To apply the general formula to the case of and use and let for all and let for all Every map can be bijectively identified with the pair (the inverse sends to the map defined by and this is technically just a change of notation). Recall that Eq. 5 ∩∪ to ∪∩ was

Expanding and simplifying the left hand side gives

and doing the same to the right hand side gives:

Thus the general identity Eq. 5 ∩∪ to ∪∩ reduces down to the previously given set equality Eq. 3b:

Distributing subtraction

 

 

 

 

(Eq. 7a)

 

 

 

 

(Eq. 7b)

       (De Morgan's law)[5]

 

 

 

 

(Eq. 7c)

       (De Morgan's law)[5]

 

 

 

 

(Eq. 7d)

The following set equalities can be deduced from the equalities 7a - 7d above (see this note on why the following equalties are atypical):

 

 

 

 

(Eq. 7e)

 

 

 

 

(Eq. 7f)

 

 

 

 

(Eq. 7g)

 

 

 

 

(Eq. 7h)

Intersections of products

If is a family of sets then

 

 

 

 

(Eq. 8)

  • Moreover, a tuple belongs to the set in Eq. 8 above if and only if for all and all

If and are two families indexed by the same set then

So for instance,

and

Intersections of products indexed by different sets

Let and be two families indexed by different sets.

Technically, implies However, sometimes these products are somehow identified as the same set through some bijection or one of these products is identified as a subset of the other via some injective map, in which case (by abuse of notation) this intersection may be equal to some other (possibly non-empty) set.

  • For example, if and with all sets equal to then and where unless, for example, is identified as a subset of through some injection, such as maybe for instance; however, in this particular case the product actually represents the -indexed product where
  • For another example, take and with and all equal to Then and which can both be identified as the same set via the bijection that sends to Under this identification,

Unions of products

For unions, only the following is guaranteed in general:

where is a family of sets.

However,

Set subtraction of products

If and are two families of sets then:

so for instance,

and

Functions and sets

Let be any function.

Let be completely arbitrary sets. Assume

Definitions

Let be any function, where we denote its domain by and denote its codomain by

Many of the identities below do not actually require that the sets be somehow related to 's domain or codomain (that is, to or ) so when some kind of relationship is necessary then it will be clearly indicated. Because of this, in this article, if is declared to be "any set," and it is not indicated that must be somehow related to or (say for instance, that it be a subset or ) then it is meant that is truly arbitrary.[note 6] This generality is useful in situations where is a map between two subsets and of some larger sets and and where the set might not be entirely contained in and/or (e.g. if all that is known about is that ); in such a situation it may be useful to know what can and cannot be said about and/or without having to introduce a (potentially unnecessary) intersection such as: and/or

Images and preimages of sets

If is any set then the image of under is defined to be the set:

while the preimage of under is:

where if is a singleton set then the filber or preimage of under is

Denote by or the image or range of which is the set:

Saturated sets

A set is said to be -saturated or a saturated set if any of the following equivalent conditions are satisfied:

  1. There exists a set such that
    • Any such set necessarily contains as a subset.
  2. and
    • The inclusion always holds, where if then this becomes

For a set to be -saturated, it is necessary that

Compositions and restrictions of functions

If and are maps then denotes the composition map

with domain and codomain

defined by

The restriction of to denoted by is the map

with defined by sending to that is,

Alternatively, where denotes the inclusion map, which is defined by

(Pre)Image of a single set

Image Preimage Additional assumptions
None
None
None
None
None
None ( and are arbitrary functions).

[6] None
None
None

Equivalences and implications of images and preimages

Image Preimage Additional assumptions on sets
implies [6] implies [6] None
if and only if None
if and only if if and only if None
if and only if if and only if and
The following are equivalent:
The following are equivalent:

If then if and only if

The following are equivalent when
  1. for some
  2. for some
The following are equivalent:
  1. and

The following are equivalent when

and
The following are equivalent:
The following are equivalent:
and
[6]

Equality holds if and only if the following is true:

  1. [7][8]

Equality holds if any of the following are true:

  1. and is surjective.

Equality holds if and only if the following is true:

  1. is -saturated.

Equality holds if any of the following are true:

  1. is injective.[7][8]

Miscellaneous

if and only if [6] if and only if

  • Thus for any [6]

(Pre)Images of set operations

Throughout, let and be any sets and let be any function.

Summary

As the table below shows, set equality is not guaranteed only for images of: intersections, set subtractions, and symmetric differences.

Image Preimage Additional assumptions on sets
[9] [4] None
[4] None
[6][4] None
[note 7] None
None

Preimages preserve set operations

Preimages of sets are well-behaved with respect to all basic set operations:

In words, preimages distribute over unions, intersections, set subtraction, and symmetric difference.

Images only preserve unions

Images of unions are well-behaved:

but images of the other basic set operations are not since only the following are guaranteed in general:

In words, images distribute over unions but not necessarily over intersections, set subtraction, or symmetric difference.

In general, equality is not guaranteed for images of set subtraction nor for images of the other two elementary set operators that can be defined as the difference of two sets:

If then where as in the more general case, equality is not guaranteed. If is surjective then which can be rewritten as: if and

Counter-examples to set equality

Picture showing failing to distribute over set intersection:
The map is defined by where denotes the real numbers. The sets and are shown in blue immediately below the -axis while their intersection is shown in green.

Examples will be given demonstrating that the set containments

might all be strict/proper; that is, equality need not hold. Specifically, the example below shows that these equalities could fail for any constant function whose domain contains at least two (distinct) points. For instance, all four containments are proper if is constant, and Thus equality is not guaranteed for even the simplest of functions.

Example: Let be any constant function with image and suppose that are non-empty disjoint subsets; that is, and which implies that all of the following sets are non-empty (and so their images under are all equal to ) and

  1. The containment is strict:

    In words: functions might not distribute over set subtraction

  2. The containment is strict:
  3. The containment is strict:

    In words: functions might not distribute over symmetric difference (which can be defined as the set subtraction of two sets: ).

  4. The containment is strict:

    In words: functions might not distribute over set intersection (which can be defined as the set subtraction of two sets: ).

What the set operations in these four examples have in common is that they either are set subtraction (examples (1) and (2)) or else they can naturally be defined as the set subtraction of two sets (examples (3) and (4)).

Mnemonic: In fact, for each of the above four set formulas for which equality is not guaranteed, the direction of the containment (that is, whether to use ) can always be deduced by imagining the function as being constant and the two sets ( and ) as being non-empty disjoint subsets of its domain. This is because every equality fails for such a function and sets: one side will be always be and the other non-empty − from this fact, the correct choice of can be deduced by answering: "which side is empty?" For example, to decide if the in

should be pretend[note 8] that is constant and that and are non-empty disjoint subsets of 's domain; then the left hand side would be empty (since ), which indicates that should be (the resulting statement is always guaranteed to be true) because this is the choice that will make

true. Alternatively, the correct direction of containment can also be deduced by consideration of any constant with and

Furthermore, this mnemonic can also be used to correctly deduce whether or not equalities such as or hold in general (although was used here, it can replaced by ). The answer to such a question can, as before, be deduced by consideration of this constant function: the answer for the general case (that is, for arbitrary and ) is always the same as the answer for this choice of (constant) function and disjoint non-empty sets.

Conditions for equality

Characterizations of when equality holds for all sets:

For any function the following statements are equivalent:

  1. is injective.
    • This means: for all distinct
  2. (The equals sign can be replaced with ).
  3. (The equals sign can be replaced with ).
  4. (The equals sign can be replaced with ).
  5. (The equals sign can be replaced with ).
  6. Any one of the four statements (b) - (e) but with the words "for all" replaced with any one of the following:
    1. "for all singleton subsets"
      • In particular, the statement that results from (d) gives a characterization of injectivity that explicitly involves only one point (rather than two): is injective if and only if
    2. "for all disjoint singleton subsets"
      • For statement (d), this is the same as: "for all singleton subsets" (because the definition of "pairwise disjoint" is satisfies vacuously by any family that consists of exactly 1 set).
    3. "for all disjoint subsets"

In particular, if a map is not known to be injective then barring additional information, there is no guarantee that any of the equalities in statements (b) - (e) hold.

An example above can be used to help prove this characterization. Indeed, comparison of that example with such a proof suggests that the example is representative of the fundamental reason why one of these four equalities in statements (b) - (e) might not hold (that is, representative of "what goes wrong" when a set equality does not hold).

Image of an intersection

Characterizations of equality: The following statements are equivalent:

    • The left hand side is always equal to (because always holds).
  1. Any of the above three conditions (g) - (i) but with the subset symbol replaced with an equals sign

Sufficient conditions for equality: Equality holds if any of the following are true:

  1. is injective.[10]
  2. The restriction is injective.
  3. [note 9]
  4. is -saturated; that is, [note 9]
  5. is -saturated; that is,
  6. or equivalently,
  7. or equivalently,
  8. or equivalently,

In addition, the following always hold:

Image of a set subtraction

Characterizations of equality: The following statements are equivalent:[proof 1]

  1. Whenever then
    • The set on the right hand side is always equal to
  2. The above condition (f) but with the symbol replaced with an equals signs

Necessary conditions for equality (excluding characterizations): If equality holds then the following are necessarily true:

  1. or equivalently
  2. or equivalently,

Sufficient conditions for equality: Equality holds if any of the following are true:

  1. is injective.
  2. The restriction is injective.
  3. [note 9] or equivalently,
  4. is -saturated; that is, [note 9]
  5. or equivalently,
Image of a set subtracted from the domain

Characterizations of equality: The following statements are equivalent:[proof 1]

  1. is -saturated.
  2. Whenever then

   where if then this list can be extended to include:

  1. is -saturated; that is,

Sufficient conditions for equality: Equality holds if any of the following are true:

  1. is injective.
  2. is -saturated; that is,
Image of a symmetric difference

Characterizations of equality: The following statements are equivalent:

  1.  and 
  2.  and 
  3.  and 
    • The inclusions and always hold.
    • If this above set equality holds, then this set will also be equal to both and
  4.  and 

Necessary conditions for equality (excluding characterizations): If equality holds then the following are necessarily true:

  1. or equivalently

Sufficient conditions for equality: Equality holds if any of the following are true:

  1. is injective.
  2. The restriction is injective.
Image of set subtraction

For any function and any sets and [proof 2]

Image of set subtraction from the domain

Taking in the above formulas gives:

where the set is equal to the image under of the largest -saturated subset of

  • In general, only always holds and equality is not guaranteed; but replacing "" with its subset "" results in a formula in which equality is always guaranteed:

    From this it follows that:[proof 1]

  • If then which can be written more symmetrically as (since ).
Image of symmetric difference

It follows from and the above formulas for the image of a set subtraction that for any function and any sets and

Image of a set

It follows from the above formulas for the image of a set subtraction that for any function and any set

This is more easily seen as being a consequence of the fact that for any if and only if

Image of set intersection

It follows from the above formulas for the image of a set that for any function and any sets and

where moreover, for any

if and only if if and only if if and only if

The sets and mentioned above could, in particular, be any of the sets or for example.

Images of preimages and preimages of images of set operations

Let and be arbitrary sets, be any map, and let and .

Image of preimage Preimage of image Additional assumptions on sets
[6] None
[11]

Equality holds if any of the following are true:

Since

Since

Using this becomes and

and so

(Pre)Images of unions and intersections

Images and preimages of unions are always preserved. Inverse images preserve both unions and intersections. It is only images of intersections that are not always preserved.

If is a family of arbitrary sets indexed by then:[6]

If all are -saturated then be will be -saturated and equality will hold in the first relation above; explicitly, this means:

 

 

 

 

(Conditional Equality 10a)

If is a family of arbitrary subsets of which means that for all then Conditional Equality 10a becomes:

 

 

 

 

(Conditional Equality 10b)

Preimage from a Cartesian product

This subsection will discuss the preimage of a subset under a map of the form For every

  • let denote the canonical projection onto and
  • let

so that which is also the unique map satisfying: for all The map should not be confused with the Cartesian product of these maps, which is by definition the map

   defined by sending   

Observation  If

If then equality will hold:

 

 

 

 

(Eq. 11a)

For equality to hold, it suffices for there to exist a family of subsets such that in which case:

 

 

 

 

(Eq. 11b)

and for all

Sequences of sets

Sequences of sets often arise in measure theory.

Definitions and notation

Throughout, will be arbitrary sets and and will denote a net or a sequence of sets where if it is a sequence then this will be indicated by either of the notations

where denotes the natural numbers. A notation indicates that is a net directed by which (by definition) is a sequence if the set which is called the net's indexing set, is the natural numbers (that is, if ) and is the natural order on

Disjoint and monotone sequences

If for all distinct indices then is called a pairwise disjoint or simply a disjoint. A sequence or net of set is called increasing or non-decreasing if (resp. decreasing or non-increasing) if for all indices (resp. ). A sequence or net of set is called strictly increasing (resp. strictly decreasing) if it is non-decreasing (resp. is non-increasing) and also for all distinct indices It is called monotone if it is non-decreasing or non-increasing and it is called strictly monotone if it is strictly increasing or strictly decreasing.

A sequences or net is said to increase to ) denoted by [12] or if is increasing and the union of all is that is, if

It is said to decrease to denoted by [12] or if is increasing and the intersection of all is that is, if

Basic properties

Ruppose that is any set such that for every index If decreases to then increases to [12] whereas if instead increases to then decreases to

If are arbitrary sets and if increases (resp. decreases) to then increase (resp. decreases) to

Partitions

Suppose that is any sequence of sets, that is any subset, and for every index let Then and is a sequence of pairwise disjoint sets.[12]

Suppose that is non-decreasing, let and let for every Then and is a sequence of pairwise disjoint sets.[12]

Families and elementwise operations

Definitions

A family of sets or simply a family is a set whose elements are sets. A family over is a family of subsets of The power set of a set is the set of all subsets of :

If are families of sets and if is any set then define:[13]

which are respectively called elementwise union, elementwise intersection, elementwise (set) difference, elementwise symmetric difference, and the trace/restriction of to The regular union, intersection, and set difference are all defined as usual and are denoted with their usual notation: and respectively. These elementwise operations on families of sets play an important role in, among other subjects, the theory of filters and prefilters on sets.

The upward closure in of a family is the family:

and the downward closure of is the family:

Categories of families of sets

A family is called isotone, ascending, or upward closed in if and [13] A family is called downward closed if

A family is said to be:

  • closed under finite intersections (resp. closed under finite unions) if whenever then (respectively, ).
  • closed under countable intersections (resp. closed under countable unions) if whenever are elements of then so is their intersections (resp. so is their union ).
  • closed under complementation in (or with respect to) if whenever then

A family of sets is called a/an:

  • π−system if and is closed under finite-intersections.
    • Every non-empty family is contained in a unique smallest (with respect to ) π−system that is denoted by and called the π−system generated by
  • filter subbase and is said to have the finite intersection property if and
  • filter on if is a family of subsets of that is a π−system, is upward closed in and is also proper, which by definition means that it does not contain the empty set as an element.
  • prefilter or filter base if it is a non-empty family of subsets of some set whose upward closure in is a filter on
  • algebra on is a non-empty family of subsets of that contains the empty set, forms a π−system, and is also closed under complementation with respect to
  • σ-algebra on is an algebra on that is closed under countable unions (or equivalently, closed under countable intersections).

Basic properties

Let and be families of sets over On the left hand sides of the following identities, is the Left most family, is in the Middle, and is the Right most set.

Commutativity:[13]

Associativity:[13]

Identity:

Domination:

See also

Notes

  1. Here "smallest" means relative to subset containment. So if is any algebra of sets containing then
  2. Since there is some such that its complement also belongs to The intersection of these two sets implies that The union of these two sets is equal to which implies that
  3. To deduce Eq. 2c from Eq. 2a, it must still be shown that so Eq. 2c is not a completely immediate consequence of Eq. 2a. (Compare this to the commentary about Eq. 3b).
  4. Let and let Let and let Then
  5. To see why equality need not hold when and are swapped, let and let and Then If and are swapped while and are unchanged, which gives rise to the sets and then In particular, the left hand side is no longer which shows that the left hand side depends on how the sets are labelled. Had instead and been swapped (with and unchanged) then both the left hand side and right hand side would have been equal to which shows that both sides depend on how the sets are labeled.
  6. So for instance, it's even possible that or that and (which happens, for instance, if ), etc.
  7. The conclusion can also be written as:
  8. Whether or not it is even feasible for the function to be constant and the sets and to be non-empty and disjoint is irrelevant for reaching the correct conclusion about whether to use
  9. Note that this condition depends entirely on and not on
  1. Let where because is also equal to As proved above, so that if and only if Since this happens if and only if Because are both subsets of the condition on the right hand side happens if and only if Because the equality holds if and only if If (such as when or ) then if and only if In particular, taking proves: if and only if where
  2. Let denote the set equality where this equality will now be proven. If then so there exists some now implies so that For the reverse inclusion, let so that there exists some such that Then so that and thus which proves that as desired. Defining the identity follows from and the inclusions

Citations

  1. Taylor, Courtney (March 31, 2019). "What Is Symmetric Difference in Math?". ThoughtCo. Retrieved 2020-09-05.
  2. Weisstein, Eric W. "Symmetric Difference". mathworld.wolfram.com. Retrieved 2020-09-05.
  3. "Algebra of sets". Encyclopediaofmath.org. 16 August 2013. Retrieved 8 November 2020.
  4. Monk 1969, pp. 24–54.
  5. Császár 1978, pp. 15–26.
  6. Császár 1978, pp. 102–120.
  7. Lee Halmos 1960, p. 39
  8. Lee Munkres 2000, p. 19
  9. Kelley 1985, p. 85
  10. See Munkres 2000, p. 21
  11. Lee p.388 of Lee, John M. (2010). Introduction to Topological Manifolds, 2nd Ed.
  12. Durrett 2019, pp. 1–8.
  13. Császár 1978, pp. 53–65.

References

This article is issued from Wikipedia. The text is licensed under Creative Commons - Attribution - Sharealike. Additional terms may apply for the media files.